Health Law
Jul 2019

Who Makes Decisions for Incapacitated Patients Who Have No Surrogate or Advance Directive?

Scott J. Schweikart, JD, MBE
AMA J Ethics. 2019;21(7):E587-593. doi: 10.1001/amajethics.2019.587.

Abstract

Unrepresented patients are those who have no surrogate or advance directive to guide medical decision making for them when they become incapacitated. While there is no perfect solution to the problem of making medical decisions for such vulnerable patients, 3 different approaches are noted in the literature: a physician approach, an ethics committee approach, and a guardianship approach. Recent policies and laws have required an approach that is “tiered” with respect to both who is involved and the gravity of the medical treatment questions at issue. In a general sense, some variant of a tiered approach is likely the best possible solution for jurisdictions and health institutions—both those already with and those without a tiered approach—to the challenging puzzle of treating unrepresented patients.

Single Greatest Category of Problems

Unrepresented patients are incapacitated individuals whom Pope describes as having “no available friends or family to make medical decisions as ‘default’ surrogates.”1 These patients typically fall into 3 groups: those who are homeless or mentally ill, those who by “choice or life history” do not have family or friends who could act as a surrogate, and those elderly patients who have outlived their family and friends.2 Indeed, the problem of addressing the “care of decisionally incapable patients” who have no surrogate to engage in the decision-making process is a bioethical puzzle and has been deemed by Karp and Wood to be “the single greatest category of problems” encountered by hospitals and clinicians.3

The United States currently faces a significant problem with regard to decision making for unrepresented patients. As recently as 2017, there were more than 70 000 unrepresented patients in the United States.1,4 However, some estimates suggest that the number may be well over 100 0001,5 and possibly as high 330 000.6 The number of unrepresented patients, already substantial, is forecasted to increase. Volpe and Steinman note, “Between 2010 and 2030, the size of this group [unrepresented patients] is expected to rise dramatically due to the aging Baby Boomer generation, the expanding population of elderly with dementia, and the growing number of seniors who live on their own.”5 Physicians frequently encounter these patients, especially in the critical care setting where determinations of withdrawing life support are at their most acute. Indeed, one study found that physicians reported considering withholding or withdrawing life support from 37% of unrepresented patients in an intensive care unit in which 16% of patients admitted were unrepresented.7 In another study, 5.5% of patients who died in ICUs were unrepresented.8

Approaches to Making Decisions

Generally, there is agreement that “a substituted judgement or a best interest standard” is best to help guide decision making for unrepresented patients,9 although laws and policies vary in how best to uphold a best interest standard.4,9 As the Hastings Center notes, “[t]here is as yet no consensus on the proper solution.”10 However, state laws and institutional policies attempt to solve the problem largely through 3 different approaches regarding the choice of decision maker: physician, ethics committee, and guardianship.5 Each of these approaches—applicable to the care of unrepresented patients generally and in specific situations such as end-of-life care—has certain advantages and disadvantages, underscoring that no one approach alone provides a solution.

Physician approach. The model of allowing the physician to be the ultimate decision maker is the main approach, with White et al’s study demonstrating that 81% of life support decisions for unrepresented patients were made “by the intensive care unit team alone or … [with] another attending physician.”8 Some states allow physicians to act as decision makers until a guardian can be appointed.11 However, it is interesting to note that 39 states do have laws that prohibit—explicitly, implicitly, or possibly—physicians from acting as a general surrogate.10 These laws prohibit physicians from becoming general surrogates in the sense that they cannot be designated or appointed a surrogate for their own patient—even for patients who have decision-making capacity and may wish to actively choose their physician as their surrogate should the need arise. As Rosoff notes, most of these laws seem to be motivated by concerns about “the possibility of a financial conflict of interest on the part of the physician.”11 Nevertheless, it is interesting to note that physicians can be the sole decision maker for unrepresented patients. Some states directly empower physicians to make decisions for unrepresented patients, like North Carolina, which will allow physicians to make end-of-life decisions for unrepresented patients without court approval as long as reasonable efforts are made to find a surrogate.11,12 Arguably, this law stands partly in contradiction to North Carolina’s statute that bars physicians from being a “health care agent” to their patient (though why lawmakers allowed such a contradiction is unclear).11,13

Ethics committee approach. Hospital ethics committees help make decisions for unrepresented patients by deliberating and then offering a recommendation. Many hospitals consult an ethics committee of their own accord; some states have laws that mandate an ethics committee’s involvement; and other states’ laws only prefer committee involvement but do not mandate it.1 The AMA Code of Medical Ethics stipulates that physicians have an “ethical responsibility” to consult an ethics committee when making decisions for those patients who lack capacity and are without an available surrogate.14 The advantage of an ethics committee is that it can, as Pope notes, “offer various perspectives and can utilize a multifaceted array of both medical and ethical considerations,” in contrast to a singular decision maker, such as a physician or guardian, who may be subject to financial incentives or bias.1

Guardianship approach. When a court determines that an individual lacks capacity to make decisions, it appoints a guardian with legal authority to make decisions for that person.1 Court appointment of a guardian to make decisions on behalf of an unrepresented patient might seem like a simple solution on its face, but it is generally disfavored and considered an inadequate solution.1 Karp and Wood note that guardianship is criticized for being “too costly, too time consuming, [and] overly cumbersome.”3 Additionally, it has been criticized because guardians often are not adequately trained and do not know the patient.1 Public guardianship (ie, guardianship created by court appointment of a person or agency unknown to the patient) may have value as the “ultimate safety net” for patients, but programs need adequate funding and staff, something that is not a reality in all states.3 The concern about adequacy of funding is echoed by Moye et al, who note that “if the public guardianship system is not adequately structured or funded, healthcare providers and hospital ethics committees are likely to be involved certainly before and sometimes after guardianship appointment.”15

Despite criticism, benefits of guardianships exist. Karp and Wood argue that public guardianship is an important option for unrepresented patients, especially those with prolonged medical issues, and note that “public guardianship should be readily available for those in need, particularly when the decision making may be ongoing.”3

Discussion

There is a significant debate in the literature about which decision-maker approach is best for unrepresented patients (both in the general sense and in more specific situations such as end-of-life care), with commentators falling into 2 basic camps: one that supports physicians and one that supports ethics committees. While there is support for guardians, the literature suggests a more prominent debate about whether physicians or ethics committees should serve as decision makers. These 2 schools of thought are illustrated in the divide between Pope (a strong advocate of ethics committees as decision makers) and Courtwright (a strong advocate of physicians as decision makers).1,2 Pope encapsulates this divide well, noting that it stems from 2 “fundamental questions”: “(1) whether the dominant ‘solo’ physician model is acceptable and, (2) if not, ‘how much’ of a second opinion [i.e. an ethics committee] is required.”16

Pope strongly argues that physicians alone should not be making treatment decisions for unrepresented patients. He explains that “when physicians don’t need to explain their treatment decisions to another decision maker, the bases for those decisions are less clearly articulated and more susceptible to the physician’s idiosyncratic treatment style.”17 Also problematic, as noted earlier, is that physicians have conflicting interests and obligations that may influence their decisions as surrogates. For example, as White et al note, physicians are perceived to have “ethical commitments to individual patients and to society at large to manage resources in a cost-conscious manner,” and when physicians become decision makers for patients, “it is unclear how they should balance the task of ‘serving two masters.’”18 Physicians can also have financial conflicts of interests that could, for example, “lead to overtreatment of patients in fee for service reimbursement models.”18 Additionally, Volpe and Steinman note that end-of-life decisions are not simply medical but “social and ethical decisions” that, if left to the physician alone, would implicitly suggest that such profound end-of-life decisions are merely “choices [that] are reducible to medical facts.”5

Nevertheless, there are strong advocates for the physician approach. Courtwright and Rubin note that physicians’ knowledge and skill, coupled with their “fiduciary duties” to the patient, make them ideal decision makers for the unrepresented, as the fiduciary duty that physicians naturally uphold “obligates them to act as the surrogate decision maker.”2

Supporters of ethics committees believe that they are less susceptible to conflicts and biases than physicians,2 although risk of bias is associated with ethics committees as well. For example, as Magelssen et al note, ethics consultants may get “incentives to provide guidance that comports with the interests of hospital management.”19 Courtwright and Rubin also note that “there is no obvious reason why an ethics committee would more accurately represent an unrepresented patient’s wishes than a treating physician.”2

A recent development in hospital policy and law is a tiered approach, which applies aspects of both the physician and the ethics committee approach in decision making for unrepresented patients. In the tiered approach, treatments and procedures are assessed and assigned to one of 3 risk categories—low-risk or routine treatment, major medical treatment, or life-sustaining treatment—as a basis for decision-making policy.1 For example, a physician may make decisions regarding low-risk treatments that are routine and in keeping with accepted medical practice standards. For medium-risk procedures that would normally require written informed consent, a physician might be required to consult with another physician or an ethics committee. The highest-risk or highest-stakes procedure, typically deemed to be withdrawing or withholding life-sustaining treatment, might require a physician to get approval and consensus from an ethics committee. These examples give a rough sketch as to how a tiered approach might function—the exact parameters and requirements vary. For example, Colorado, New York State, and Montana have instituted statutes with a tiered approach similar to that just described.1,4 The Cleveland Clinic has also generated a similar institutional policy based on 3 risk categories: routine care, decisions for which informed consent would ordinarily be needed, and decisions about withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining treatment.20 Smith and Luck describe the Cleveland Clinic policy as a “gradation of various safeguards” put into “place as the significance and consequences of the clinical decisions increase.”20

Conclusion

A collaborative, multidisciplinary approach to the problem of unrepresented patients, although imperfect, is preferable to a unilateral approach. As Moye et al argue, “collaboration is key to illuminate their [unrepresented patients’] needs and rights,” while providing a “menu of options” that involves all 3 of the major decision-making approaches: physicians, ethics committees, and guardianship.15 Taking this collaborative approach (which includes guardianship) and combining it with a tiered approach (which strikes a balance between physicians and ethics committees) creates a multifaceted decision-making method, involving layers of options and ethical safeguards, thus making it likely the best possible solution to this most vexing of bioethical quandaries.

References

  1. Pope TM. Unbefriended and unrepresented: better medical decision making for incapacitated patients without healthcare surrogates. Ga Stat Univ Law Rev. 2017;33(4):923-1019.
  2. Courtwright A, Rubin E. Who should decide for the unrepresented? Bioethics. 2016:30(3):173-180.

  3. Karp N, Wood E. Incapacitated and alone: healthcare decision-making for the unbefriended elderly. American Bar Association Commission on Law and Aging. https://www.americanbar.org/content/dam/aba/administrative/law_aging/2003_Unbefriended_Elderly_Health_Care_Descision-Making7-11-03.authcheckdam.pdf. Published July 2003. Accessed January 8, 2019.

  4. Sequeira AL, Lewis A. Ethical and legal considerations in the management of an unbefriended patient in a vegetative state. Neurocrit Care. 2017;27(2):173-179.
  5. Volpe RL, Steinman D. Peeking inside the black box: one institution’s experience developing policy for unrepresented patients. Hamline Law Rev. 2013;36(2):265-274.
  6. Kim H, Song M. Medical decision-making for adults who lack decision-making capacity and a surrogate: state of the science. Am J Hosp Palliat Care. 2018;35(9):1227-1234.
  7. White DB, Curtis JR, Lo B, Luce JM. Decisions to limit life-sustaining treatment for critically ill patients who lack both decision-making capacity and surrogate decision-makers. Crit Care Med. 2006;34(8):2053-2059.
  8. White DB, Curtis JR, Wolf LE, et al. Life support for patients without a surrogate decision maker: who decides? Ann Intern Med. 2007;147(1):34-40.

  9. Courtwright AM, Abrams J, Robinson EM. The role of a hospital ethics consultation service in decision-making for unrepresented patients. J Bioeth Inq. 2017;14(2):241-250.
  10. Hastings Center. Guidelines on the Termination of Life-Sustaining Treatment and the Care of the Dying. Briarcliff Manor, NY: Hastings Center; 1987.

  11. Rosoff PM, Leong KM. An ethical and legal framework for physicians as surrogate decision-makers for their patients. J Law Med Ethics. 2015;43(4):857-877.
  12. NC Gen Stat §90-322 (2016).

  13. NC Gen Stat §32A-18 (2016).

  14. American Medical Association. Opinion 2.1.2 Decisions for adult patients who lack capacity. Code of Medical Ethics. https://www.ama-assn.org/delivering-care/ethics/decisions-adult-patients-who-lack-capacity. Accessed January 14, 2018.

  15. Moye J, Catlin C, Kwak J, Wood E, Teaster PB. Ethical concerns and procedural pathways for patients who are incapacitated and alone: implications from a qualitative study for advancing ethical practice. HEC Forum. 2017;29(2):171-189.
  16. Pope TM. Legal briefing: adult orphans and the unbefriended: making medical decisions for unrepresented patients without surrogates. J Clin Ethics. 2015;26(2):180-188.
  17. Pope TM. Making medical decisions for patients without surrogates. N Engl J Med. 2013;369(21):1976-1978.
  18. White DB, Jonsen A, Lo B. Ethical challenge: when clinicians act as surrogates for unrepresented patients. Am J Crit Care. 2012;21(3):202-207.
  19. Magelssen M, Pedersen R, Førde R. Sources of bias in clinical ethics case deliberation. J Med Ethics. 2014;40(10):678-682.
  20. Smith ML, Luck CL. Desperately seeking a surrogate—for a patient lacking decision-making capacity. Narrat Inq Bioeth. 2014;4(2):161-169.

Citation

AMA J Ethics. 2019;21(7):E587-593.

DOI

10.1001/amajethics.2019.587.

Conflict of Interest Disclosure

The author(s) had no conflicts of interest. 

The viewpoints expressed in this article are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views and policies of the AMA.