Medicine and Society
Oct 2019

How Should Decision Aids Be Used During Counseling to Help Patients Who Are “Genetically at Risk”?

Natalie Evans, PhD, Suzanne Metselaar, PhD, Carla van El, PhD, Nina Hallowell, DPhil, MA, and Guy Widdershoven, PhD
AMA J Ethics. 2019;21(10):E865-872. doi: 10.1001/amajethics.2019.865.

Abstract

People with genetic predispositions to disease are faced with uncertainty about whether, when, and to what extent an illness will actually develop. This prognostic uncertainty, combined with knowledge that preventative interventions (eg, risk-reducing surgeries for familial cancer syndromes) could significantly affect people’s lives, renders prevention decisions especially challenging. This article illuminates ethical questions about the use of decision aids for people with genetic predispositions and calls for approaching individual decisions in light of ongoing communication and reflection about a person’s life goals and values.

 

Everyone who is born holds dual citizenship, in
the kingdom of the well and in the kingdom of
the sick. Although we all prefer to use only the
good passport, sooner or later each of us is
obliged, at least for a spell, to identify ourselves
as citizens of that other place.

                                                       Susan Sontag1

Decision Making and Genetic Risk

As Sontag’s quote boldly illustrates, health and illness are generally seen as dichotomous categories: one is either sick or healthy. Yet the rapid development and implementation of genomic medicine is challenging this duality by increasing the presence of yet another type of “citizenship”—namely, for those who are “genetically at-risk.”2 In dealing with this new category, health services face several challenges, including how to communicate complex information on individual and familial risk and how to support decision making on preventative treatment options.3

As people become increasingly aware of their genetic predispositions, more will face decisions about prevention efforts such as lifestyle changes and risk-reducing treatments (eg, surgeries for familial cancer syndromes). Prevention efforts might involve difficult trade-offs between quality of life and risk reduction, because in some cases reducing risk of future ill-health is only possible with some sacrifice of current quality of life. Furthermore, in the case of genetic predispositions, people are faced with uncertainty about whether, when, and the extent to which an illness might actually develop. This prognostic uncertainty, combined with the fact that any preventative treatments might significantly affect people’s lives, renders decision making about such interventions especially challenging. It is therefore all the more important that these decisions take into account people’s norms, values, and life goals.4,5,6 This article examines the need for genetic counseling and decision aids for people with genetic predispositions and calls for innovation in both communication processes and decision aids in order to embed individual decisions in a broader process of ongoing reflection on personal life goals and values.

Genetic Counseling

Current decision-making supports in the context of genetic risk are proving inadequate. Genetic counselors help patients to assess their genetic risk and consider interventions in a nondirective way, which entails providing complete and unbiased information, refraining from revealing their own preferences,7,8 and helping align care with a patient’s and family’s values.9 Genetic counseling services are, however, in high demand, and care and treatment discussions about genetic risk are increasingly occurring outside of the genetic counselling setting, particularly in primary care,10,11 oncology,11 and surgery.12 Patients also discuss known genetic risks with a variety of health professionals—not all of whom are well informed about patients’ stated goals and values.13 For example, in the case of patients with BRCA 1 and 2 familial cancer syndromes, the availability of multiple (preventative) treatment and screening options means that some patients with a mutation are cared for by a succession of health care professionals in general practice; clinical genetics; and screening, reproductive, and surgical services. Specialization and fragmentation of care can lead to piecemeal, incomplete, and conflicting information about care and treatment options.

In response to the growing need to support communication and decision making in the context of genetic risk in different clinical settings, a variety of decision aids have been developed. For example, in the case of familial cancer syndromes, decision aids have been developed for diagnostic genetic testing,14 reproductive decisions,15 and preventative treatment decisions.16,17 Decisions about how to respond to genetic risk, however, pose ethical questions that call for innovation. In what follows, we discuss the goals and ethical challenges of using decision aids in the context of genetic risk.

Need for Innovating Decision Aids

Decision aids have been developed for “preference sensitive” decisions, for which the best option depends on a patient’s perception of an optimal trade-off between harms and benefits.18 They have been designed to increase patient participation in decision making and to enhance rather than replace patient-professional communication. Decision aids have 3 principle goals: to improve patient understanding of risks and benefits, to help patients clarify their values, and to help patients make decisions consistent with those values.18 Their development should be guided by decision science, which assumes that, in any given context, a best decision can be revealed—or at least approximated—by using a decision-making process or model.19 Risks that deserve ethical and clinical consideration include decontextualization, detachment, and fragmentation.

Decontextualization. A patient’s familial, social, and cultural context are rarely considered in the development of genomic medicine decision aids, despite evidence suggesting that preference-sensitive decisions are influenced by patients’ perceptions of successes or failures of approaches taken by other family members with the same condition,20,21,22 by perceptions of familial responsibility (eg, parents can be more inclined to choose aggressive preventative options),23 and by attitudes and preferences of partners or members of their social networks.24 Decision aids’ underlying assumptions and value clarification methods (eg, utility theory in decision tree analysis)25 could muddle a patient’s decision-making process or be incompatible with a patient’s normal decision-making style. Put differently, decision aids can impose a system on the decision-making process that alienates a patient from his or her lifeworld of shared social experience.26

Detachment. Using decision aids to guide patients’ decisions might be particularly tempting in situations in which it is impossible for clinicians to know whether a patient will develop a disease. This uncertainty could lead some clinicians to delegate to a decision aid the tasks of providing risk information, describing options, and clarifying values. The tendency to “retreat behind a technique”27 in the face of ethically and emotionally difficult communication has been described in other areas of health care.28,29 Busy health care professionals might also consider the preferences- and values-clarification exercises associated with decision aids an adequate exploration of a patient’s values. However, decision aids’ effectiveness in elucidating patients’ values remains unclear,25,30 and using them to replace rather than enhance discussion of a patient’s values and preferences is clinically and ethically problematic.

Fragmentation. Technological advances in genetic sequencing mean that future generations could know their genetic predispositions earlier in life and thus might require support from clinicians to reflect on their life goals and to plan care.31 Potentially new developments, such as newborn whole genome sequencing, might result in people learning about genes of lesser penetrance (ie, lower risk of developing disease) and receiving polygenetic risk scores for a range of common diseases. As genomic medicine goes mainstream, the number of “patients” with knowledge of their genetic risks from a young age will increase. When people are aware from a young age of their genetic risks, they can experience pressure to anticipate and plan life events32 and future preventative interventions.22 Furthermore, many of these patients, as in the example of BRCA 1 and 2 mutation carriers, will see a host of health care professionals in relation to their genetic risk over the course of their life. Currently, however, decision aids are not developed to facilitate long-term planning or support continuity of care across different settings and with different health care professionals.

In summary, using decision aids in the process of decision making in the context of genetic risk involves considerable risks of decontextualization, detachment from ethically and emotionally difficult discussions, and fragmentation of decisions. These 3 risks are interrelated and reflect a need to understand and discuss a person’s biography, context, and treatment trajectory and to anticipate care needs and provide continuity of care.

Dealing With Decision Aids’ Risks

Although we cautiously encourage the use of decision aids in the context of genetic risk, we make the following recommendations to minimize the risks outlined above. To minimize decontextualization, we recommend embedding decision-aid use meaningfully into ongoing patient-clinician communications in which a patient’s familial, social, and cultural context and other influences are explored and in which opportunities to include family members and loved ones in the decision-making process are presented. Genetic counselors have unique skills and expertise in familial-based counseling that enable them to assume responsibility for this change, although there is a role for nurse navigators, case managers, or even technological solutions such as patient pathway applications. To minimize some clinicians’ detachment from ethically and emotionally complex discussions, we recommend meeting clinicians’ unmet genetics education needs10 with training in how to communicate about genetic risk and in how to use decision aids appropriately. Finally, to minimize fragmentation of decisions among clinicians, the values and preferences a patient shares and explores with one health professional should be available to another.

Experiences of advance care planning for end-of-life care can inform how clinicians plan personalized care and treatment trajectories informed by patient preferences and values within the context of genetic risk. As is the case for successful advance care planning initiatives,33 health professionals will need to be convinced of the importance of elucidating and respecting patient preferences and values and of ensuring that information is up-to-date and available in health record systems. We also recommend assessing decision aids’ value as perceived by patients over the course of their care trajectory and not just assessing their effectiveness in facilitating comprehension or in improving procedural, psychological, or functional measures in the context of individual decisions. Innovations in the design and use of decision aids for people with genetic predispositions will require educating patients and clinicians about interventions and options from a life-course perspective and fostering carriers’ reflection on their values, preferences, and life goals across the entire care trajectory.

References

  1. Sontag S. Illness as Metaphor. New York, NY: Farrar Straus & Giroux; 1978.

  2. Manolio TA, Chisholm RL, Ozenberger B, et al. Implementing genomic medicine in the clinic: the future is here. Genet Med. 2013;15(4):258-267.
  3. Weitzel JN, Blazer KR, MacDonald DJ, et al. Genetics, genomics, and cancer risk assessment: state of the art and future directions in the era of personalized medicine. CA Cancer J Clin. 2011;61(5):327-359.
  4. Kvåle K, Bondevik M. What is important for patient centred care? A qualitative study about the perceptions of patients with cancer. Scand J Caring Sci. 2008;22(4):582-589.
  5. Lee YK, Low WY, Ng CJ. Exploring patient values in medical decision making: a qualitative study. PLoS One. 2013;8(11):e80051.

  6. Lang E, Bell NR, Dickinson JA, et al. Eliciting patient values and preferences to inform shared decision making in preventive screening. Can Fam Physician. 2018;64(1):28-31.
  7. Rehmann-Sutter C. Why non-directiveness is insufficient: ethics of genetic decision making and a model of agency. Med Stud. 2009;1(2):113-129.
  8. Kirklin D. Framing, truth telling and the problem with non-directive counselling. J Med Ethics. 2007;33(1):58-62.
  9. Howard AF, Balneaves LG, Bottorff JL, Rodney P. Preserving the self: the process of decision making about hereditary breast cancer and ovarian cancer risk reduction. Qual Health Res. 2011;21(4):502-519.
  10. Houwink EJ, van Luijk SJ, Henneman L, van der Vleuten C, Jan Dinant G, Cornel MC. Genetic educational needs and the role of genetics in primary care: a focus group study with multiple perspectives. BMC Fam Pract. 2011;12(1):5.

  11. Douma KF, Smets EM, Allain DC. Non-genetic health professionals’ attitude towards, knowledge of and skills in discussing and ordering genetic testing for hereditary cancer. Fam Cancer. 2016;15(2):341-350.
  12. Klitzman R, Chung W. The process of deciding about prophylactic surgery for breast and ovarian cancer: patient questions, uncertainties, and communication. Am J Med Genet A. 2010;152A(1):52-66.
  13. Rubin LR, Werner-Lin A, Sagi M, et al. “The BRCA clock is ticking!”: negotiating medical concerns and reproductive goals in preimplantation genetic diagnosis. Hum Fertil (Camb). 2014;17(3):159-164.
  14. Wakefield CE, Meiser B, Homewood J, et al; Australian GENetic Testing Decision Aid Collaborative Group. A randomized trial of a breast/ovarian cancer genetic testing decision aid used as a communication aid during genetic counseling. Psychooncology. 2008;17(8):844-854.

  15. PGD Nederland. Beslissingsondersteuning voor mensen met erfelijke kanker en een kinderwens [Decision support for people with hereditary cancer and a desire to have children]. https://www.pgdnederland.nl/beslissingsondersteuning-voor-mensen-met-erfelijke-kanker-en-een-kinderwens. Accessed December 12, 2018.

  16. Culver JO, MacDonald DJ, Thornton AA, et al. Development and evaluation of a decision aid for BRCA carriers with breast cancer. J Genet Couns. 2011;20(3):294-307.
  17. Harmsen MG, Steenbeek MP, Hoogerbrugge N, et al. A patient decision aid for risk-reducing surgery in premenopausal BRCA1/2 mutation carriers: development process and pilot testing. Health Expect. 2018;21(3):659-667.
  18. Edwards A, Elwyn G. Shared Decision-Making in Health Care: Achieving Evidence-Based Patient Choice. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 2009.

  19. Roy B. Decision science or decision-aid science? Eur J Oper Res. 1993;66(2):184-203.

  20. Hamilton R, Williams JK, Bowers BJ, Calzone K. Life trajectories, genetic testing, and risk reduction decisions in 18-39 year old women at risk for hereditary breast and ovarian cancer. J Genet Couns. 2009;18(2):147-159.
  21. Hamilton RJ, Innella NA, Bounds DT. Living with genetic vulnerability: a life course perspective. J Genet Couns. 2016;25(1):49-61.
  22. Singh K, Lester J, Karlan B, Bresee C, Geva T, Gordon O. Impact of family history on choosing risk-reducing surgery among BRCA mutation carriers. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2013;208(4):329.el-329.e6.
  23. Dean M. “It’s not if I get cancer, it’s when I get cancer”: BRCA-positive patients’ (un)certain health experiences regarding hereditary breast and ovarian cancer risk. Soc Sci Med. 2016;163:21-27.

  24. Hesse-Biber S, An C. Genetic testing and post-testing decision making among BRCA-positive mutation women: a psychosocial approach. J Genet Couns. 2016;25(5):978-992.
  25. Charles C, Gafni A, Whelan T, O’Brien MA. Treatment decision aids: conceptual issues and future directions. Health Expect. 2005;8(2):114-125.
  26. Habermas J. Reason and the Rationalization of Society. McCarthy T, trans. Boston, MA: Beacon Press; 1984. The Theory of Communicative Action; vol 1.

  27. Saunders CM, Baines M. Living With Dying: The Management of Terminal Disease. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1983.

  28. McNamara B, Waddell C, Colvin M. Threats to the good death: the cultural context of stress and coping among hospice nurses. Sociol Health Illn. 1995;17(2):222-241.
  29. Gunaratnam Y. Intercultural palliative care: do we need cultural competence? Int J Palliat Nurs. 2007;13(10):470-477.

  30. Nelson WL, Han PK, Fagerlin A, Stefanek M, Ubel PA. Rethinking the objectives of decision aids: a call for conceptual clarity. Med Decis Making. 2007;27(5):609-618.
  31. Cheng TL, Cohn RD, Dover GJ. The genetics revolution and primary care pediatrics. JAMA. 2008;299(4):451-453.
  32. Meissen GJ, Berchek RL. Intended use of predictive testing by those at risk for Huntington disease. Am J Med Genet. 1987;26(2):283-293.
  33. Collins LG, Parks SM, Winter L. The state of advance care planning: one decade after SUPPORT. Am J Hosp Palliat Care. 2006;23(5):378-384.

Citation

AMA J Ethics. 2019;21(10):E865-872.

DOI

10.1001/amajethics.2019.865.

Conflict of Interest Disclosure

The author(s) had no conflicts of interest to disclose.

The viewpoints expressed in this article are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views and policies of the AMA.